II BARCELONA WORKSHOP ON ISSUES IN THE THEORY OF
REFERENCE
Special topic: TWO-DIMENTIONALISM
ABSTRACTS
Invited
talks:
DAVID
J. CHALMERS
University of Arizona, USA
<chalmers@arizona.edu>
"The
foundations of two-dimensional semantics"
The central importance of the two-dimensional
semantic framework is that it promises to yield notions of meaning and possibility
that are closely tied to reason and cognition. But many different versions of
the two-dimensional framework have been put forward, and it is not clear how
these are related. In this paper, I try to shed light on this matter by
distinguishing from first principles different ways of interpreting the
framework. The central distinction is between contextual interpretations, which
use the framework to model context-dependence, and epistemic interpretations,
which use the framework to model epistemic dependence. Contextual
interpretations are more common, but I argue that only an epistemic
interpretation can yield constitutive connections among reason, meaning, and
possibility.
I develop an epistemic version of
the two-dimensional framework in some detail, compare it to other versions, and
show how it can be used to address a number of important problems in the
philosophy of language and mind.
MICHAEL
MARTIN
University College London, UK
<michael.martin@ucl.ac.uk>
"Objects
of Desire"
Discussions of indexicality and the
psychological phenomenon of perspective commonly divorce treatments of this
aspect of thought from truth-conditions. Stalnaker's diagonal proposition
offers a means of respecting the distinctive features of indexicality within a
truth-conditional approach and Higginbotham in recent work has exploited a
similar model to explain the nature of tensed thought. In this paper I argue
that there are some aspects of the perspectival nature of attitudes towards
time which require us to acknowledge that there are subpropositional
psychological states. Reflecting on Arthur Prior's famous example of 'Thank
Goodness that's over', I argue that we need to recognise a distinction between
desires for acts or events and desires for propositions. The former occupy a
cycle of motivation in a way that the latter cannot. We can explain the
psychological difference here by reference to a difference in the content of
desires once we acknowledge that act and event desires in contrast to
propositional desires are related to sub propositional objects which do not
specify a time.
ROBERT
STALNAKER
Massachusetts Institue of Technology, USA
<stal@MIT.EDU>
"Conceptual
and Metaphysical Necessity"
Saul Kripke made a persuasive case that there are necessary a posteriori and
contingent a priori truths, but philosophers have disagreed about the
significance of the phenomena that he drew to our attention. Frank Jackson and
David Chalmers have argued that there are no irreducible necessary a posteriori truths, and have used a two-dimensional
modal semantic framework to make precise a way of explaining all necessity in
terms of conceptual necessity. But I argue that while the two-dimensional
framework gives a useful representation of the phenomena, their reductive
account does not succeed. I contrast two interpretations of the framework, one
modeled on David Kaplan’s semantics for demonstratives and the other - the
metasemantic interpretation -in which the second dimension represents the way
that the contents of thoughts and expressions depend on the facts. I argue that
the first interpretation requires implausible assumptions about the nature of
intentionality to explain the facts. The second interpretation, I argue, gives
a better account of the phenomena, an account that neither requires nor
provides any explanation for a notion of purely conceptual truth that is
knowable a priori.
Contributed
talks:
PAUL
BLOOMFIELD
University of Connecticut, USA
<phsb@uconn.edu>
"Lets Be Realistic About Serious
Metaphysics"
The main thesis is that "serious metaphysics"
(Jackson's term) ought to be focusing only on possibilities which are centered
on or indexed to the actual world and ought to ignore possibilities not fixed
by what is actually possible. Thus, conceptual analysis performed upon
"primary" or "A" meanings, when used as a means to gain a
priori knowledge of reality, leads metaphysics astray. Locke's distinction
between real and nominal essence is
compared to the primary/A - secondary/C distinction between meanings and a
dilemma is presented for the defenders of using logically possible zombies as
informing our understanding of actual consciousness. The discussion focuses on
the work of Locke, Putnam, Kripke, Chalmers and Jackson.
EMMA
BORG
University of Reading, England
<e.g.n.borg@reading.ac.uk>
"Demonstrative
content and character in semantics and epistemology"
This paper explores how to incorporate the kind
of two-aspect theory of meaning for demonstratives familiar from Kaplan within
the kind of truth-conditional semantic theory familiar from Davidson. The options for accommodating the elements of
the theory of direct reference range from pre- (or meta-) semantics, semantics
itself, through to post-semantics (or pragmatics); Kaplan himself endorses the
middle road. I argue that this position
is clearly correct for character (following arguments concerning complex
demonstratives) and thus explore how to accommodate it within a
truth-conditional semantic theory. The
status of content is, however, claimed to be less clearly semantic:
specifically, I argue that, were we to embrace any epistemically-laden (e.g.
acquaintance-based) approach to content, it would properly belong to the
post-semantic realm. The argument here
turns on the nature of deferred demonstratives – expressions which demand referential
semantic analysis but flout any suitable epistemic condition. Instead, then, we need to recognise a far
thinner notion of content (as Kaplan himself clearly did), one which recognises
that the contents of our thoughts may be sensitive to the syntactic forms we
use to express them. Only if singular
content is understood in this thin way, do we have something which can be
treated as properly semantic.
RICHARD
BREHENY
RCEAL, University of Cambridge, UK
<reb35@cam.ac.uk>
"Anaphoric pronouns and context
sets"
This paper concerns itself with non-dynamic
approaches to discourses like in (1), focussing on the anaphoric dependence
between the pronoun and the indefinite.
(1) a. Last night I met a member of the
Cabinet. He was pro‑Europe.
b. I
predicted that a woman will be nominated for president. Also, I predict she
will win.
The question it poses is whether, in analysing
such discourses, Stalnaker's descriptive framework employing sets of
possibilities for context and content offers any distinct advantages over
frameworks in which the content of utterances and what is presupposed can be
represented by other means. It could be suggested that Stalnaker's framework
would have the edge if a semantic analysis of pronouns according to which they
are treated as variables terms of direct reference could be sustained. After
considering the pragmatics of such discourses in somewhat more detail than in
Stalnaker (1998), it will be argued that a treatment of pronouns as definite
(as in E‑type approaches) would in fact be required. As other frameworks
can deal with such discourses using an E‑type approach, the conclusion
will be that Stalnaker's framework does not offer any advantage.
ALEX
BYRNE & JAMES PRYOR
MIT, USA,
<abyrne@MIT.EDU>
Harvard, USA, <jpryor@fas.harvard.edu>
"Bad
Intensions"
According to two-dimensionalists like David
Chalmers, words like "water" and "Bob Dylan" have two sorts
of intensions, a "primary" or "epistemic" intension and a
"secondary" or "metaphysical" intension. The
"epistemic" intension of a word does the most theoretical work, and
can be thought of as a set of properties that all competent speakers associate
with the word, that fixes the word's reference, and that accounts for the
word's cognitive significance. However, it is prima facie unlikely that words
have such epistemic intensions. We rehearse Kripke's familiar arguments from
ignorance and error, which seem to show that competent speakers need not
associate any informative and uniquely identifying properties with their words.
We then examine and criticize some of Chalmers' responses to these arguments.
MAITE EZCURDIA
Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, UNAM, México
<maite@filosoficas.unam.mx>
"Occurrrences
Revisited"
In this paper, I deal with the issue of the sort of entities that
constitute the primary bearers of reference and truth-conditions where
indexicals and indexical-sentences are concerned. I side with Kaplan, against
utterance accounts, in thinking that they are combinations of syntactical
expressions and contexts, or what he has called “occurrences”. The view I
defend differs from other occurrence theories in two crucial respects: it
incorporates the completers of demonstratives as one of the parameters against
which they obtain a referent, and the resulting linguistic meaning of a
demonstrative cannot be represented as a unary function from contexts to
truth-conditional contribution. By introducing the completers of demonstratives
into the context, the view defended is empirically adequate in ways in which
other occurrence theories are not.
Of the three arguments
presented by occurrence-theorists against utterance views, namely, those
dealing with the lack of expressions problem, the logic problem and the
non-uttering problem, I argue that the responses that an occurrence theory
should give of them are not always the standard ones. On the non-uttering
problem, I argue that there is no situation in which “I am not uttering
anything” is true, and that occurrence-theorists are committed to saying this
given the way in which contexts are construed from speech situations. On the
lack of expressions problem, I take the standard line from
occurrence-theorists, but the line I take on the logic problem is neither
standard nor simple. I argue that although we may not have any pressing need
from the tasks of logic itself to account for inferences of the form p therefore p, where p is an indexical sentence, reasonings
of a similar form do occur in natural language. I defend this claim by
developing the idea of semantic possibility, and argue that a semantic theory of indexicals that
allows for accounts of why such forms of reasoning are valid are preferable
over others like utterance-style theories which, as a matter of principle,
cannot. In this way, I seek to respond to the dilemma set forth by
García-Carpintero to occurrence theories, viz. to either give an empirically
adequate account of demonstratives or be faced with the logic problem. The view
here defended is empirically adequate in the way required by the dilemma and although
it may respond to the logic problem as stated by Kaplan, I argue that the
challenge to theories of indexicals does not come from tasks set forth by logic
but by semantics.
ROBIN
JESHION
University of Southern California, Los Angeles,
USA
<jeshion@rcf-fs.usc.edu>
"Descriptive
Descriptive Names"
Descriptive names are names whose reference is fixed exclusively with the use
of a definite description. Acquaintance plays no role. Analysis of descriptive
names is typically subordinated to and constrained by the analyses of the
semantics and psycho-semantics of ordinary names. This basic attitude is rooted
in two widely shared views about descriptive names. One is that descriptive
names are extremely rare in natural language. The other is that we are always
free to introduce a descriptive name just by stipulating "Let 'N' refer to
the F". Gareth Evans relied upon these two points in developing his
influential analyses of descriptive names as abbreviations for rigidified
descriptions. In this essay, I criticize his theory, and, more importantly,
attempt to show that the basic attitude about descriptive names is misguided.
Descriptive names should not automatically be taken as having a lesser status
in theorizing than ordinary, ostensive names, for they are not particularly
rare and cannot be "artificially" created. I use this criticism as a
springboard for presenting an alternative semantics and psycho-semantics of
descriptive names, one which forces us to alter our understanding of de re
thought.
TOMIS
KAPITAN
Northern Illinois University, USA
<kapitan@niu.edu>
"Indexical Execution"
According to a standard account of indexicals,
the meaning of an indexical type can be displayed by a rule indicating how the
designations of its tokens are fixed in terms of facts about their utterances.
So viewed, the context-sensitivity of indexicals is partly a matter of
token-reflexivity or utterance-reflexivity. But while such reflexivity is
essential to interpreting indexical tokens, it is not a factor in a speaker's
identificatory use of indexicals. Tokens cannot be interpreted unless they are
first produced, and obviously, the speaker who produces them does not depend
upon utterance parameters in order to identify their referents. Thus, the
standard account cannot explain a speaker's execution of indexical reference.
Instead, we must acknowledge a fundamental duality of meaning for every
indexical type, executive and interpretative, each of which operates on
contextual elements to roduce the individuating modes needed for identification. But whereas contexts of utterance are
suitable for interpretation, executive identification depends upon
psychological contexts constituted by speakers' perspectives. The notion of
perspective is explained, and an analysis of individuating executive mechanisms
is given that preserves the threefold distinction between meaning, mode, and
referent, and the functional representation of indexical meaning.
PHILIPP
KELLER
Université de Genève, Switzerland
<
"n-Dimensionalism"
Whether or not you can conceive that p
depends on your epistemic situation. Your epistemic situation depends on the
world you are in. This much is uncontroversial. More important is that a
complete description of your epistemic situation also includes what you know
or even what you are in a position to
know about the world you are in. Not all of this knowledge can be stripped
off while determining truth or falsity of this-wordly statements in
counterfactual circumstances. This undermines a distinction between considering a possible world as
counterfactual and considering a
possible world as actual in terms of what you keep fixed (only the language
or your concepts or empirical knowledge as well) and the associated distinction
between primary and secondary intensions. To "retain the concept of the real actual world'', I will argue, we
have to make assumptions about how the real world is like. These assumptions
trivialize what we can find out about what is a priori in this way.
Conditionalizing on these assumptions paves the way to a more general outlook
on the a priori: n-dimensionalism.
GÖTZ-A.
KLAGES & ARMIN TATZEL
Univ. Hamburg , Germany. <gak@mediascape.de>
Université de Genève , Switzerland. <armin.tatzel@lettres.unige.ch>
"The
World According to Pierre"
What we call the egocentric view of belief attribution is
the idea that, roughly, the success of such attributions is dependent on
certain conditions of fit between the
ways the attributer and the subject of the attribution conceptualise the things
and properties the attributed belief is about. One of the traits which make the
egocentric view attractive is that it provides an explanation of the troubles
we face when we try to attribute beliefs to people who conceptualise the
relevant things or properties in a way which differs largely from our own.
Kripke's Pierre is an example of this kind.
Egocentric views of belief attribution
might be formulated in different theoretical frameworks. In the talk we compare
two possible egocentric theories: one formulated in terms of structured
propositions and one formulated in the framework of Stalnaker's two-dimensional
theory of communication. Using the Pierre case as an example we discuss the
explanations the two egocentric theories provide for the troubles which arise
if we try to attribute beliefs to Pierre. We argue that Stalnaker's theory
provides the most natural framework for the egocentric view.
MICHAELIS
MICHAEL
The University of New South Wales, Australia
<m.michael@unsw.edu.au>
"The
Problems of Double Indexing accounts of The A priori"
Some have sought to domesticate the notion of the a priori by finding a model
of it in the more readily accepted space of alethic modality, a model which
crucially uses double indexing. In these attempts it is usual to identify the
set of a priori interpreted sentences with the set of sentences with a
necessary diagonal. These attempts have yielded at best partial accounts. What
is common to these accounts is a failure to build in the epistemic aspect of the
a priori. But the a priori is essentially epistemic. The distinction between
the a priori and the a posteriori does not partition the set of truths of an
interpreted language, even relative to a speaker and a context. Rather that
distinction partitions the set of knowable truths. If there are truths which
are unknowable then those truths are neither a priori nor a posteriori
knowable. Yet if there are mathematical truths of this sort they will have
necessary diagonals and yet not be a priori because they are unknowable.
MARTINE
NIDA-RUEMELIN
University of Fribourg , Switzerland
<martine.nida@-ruemelin@unifr.ch>
"Phenomenal
Concepts"
After a brief introduction of the
distinction between phenomenal and non-phenomenal belief with respect to
qualia proposed in earlier papers (see
e.g. my "On Belief about experiences. (...)" Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 1997) I use the two-dimensional framework to account
for the difference in content between phenomenal and non-phenomenal belief in a way based on ideas of David Chalmers
(see David Chalmers, "Content and Epistemology of Phenomenal Belief",
accessible in the internet). Phenomenal belief with respect to the quale blue
(that can be had only by people acquainted with that quale) involves what Chalmers
calls the purely phenomenal concept of blue. The two-dimensional function that
characterizes the purely phenomenal concept of blue associates this specific
quale independently of the world taken as actual and independently of the world
taken as counterfactual (the concept is thus what one might call a superrigid
designator). By contrast, the two-dimensional function corresponding to the
relational concept of blue involved in nonphenomenal belief about the quale
blue (which can be had by someone who is not acquainted with that quale) is
either dependent on the world taken as actual or non-rigid. The description of
the subjective content of phenomenal and non-phenomenal belief content proposed (content according to
primary intensions) may be used to give a precise account of the intuitive idea
that the fact expressed by "A has an experience of blue" can be
grasped only by someone who is acquainted with blue: The subjective content of
the phenomenal belief that A has an experience of blue (but not of the corresponding
non-phenomenal belief) can be represented by the set of possible worlds that
also represents the content (according to secondary intensions) of the sentence
"A has an experience of blue".
JÉROME
PELLETIER
Université de Bretagne Occidentale , France
"Two-dimensionalism, Simulation and
Fiction"
<jerome.pelletier@univ-brest.fr>
In this paper, I study ‘unofficial uses of the
first person pronoun’ such as in (1) ‘If I were you, I would stay away from
me’. I distinguish between the ‘official content’ and the ‘unofficial content’
of (1). Contrary to the official content of (1) which is located at the level
of words, its unofficial content is a property of utterances of (1) and it
violates in the consequent of the conditional the rule that ‘I’ refers to the
speaker. Since the aim of conditionals of the ‘If I were you’ kind is usually
to give practical advises, I then try to give an analysis of the kind of
imaginative project involved in advising. It appears that advising supposes an
imaginative projection into the other’s situation without commiting the adviser
as to what he or she will do when such a situation arises. On that basis, I
compare the merits and limits of two analysis of (1), that is an anaphoric
proposal and a pretense theoretic proposal. I try to show that the only
adequate explanation of conditional statements prefaced with an ‘If I were you’
sentence should lead us to make a minor improvement in 2-Dimensionalist theory
of the reference of pure indexicals in order to take into account the
possibility of context-shift through pretense .
FRANCOIS
RECANATI
Institut Jean-Nicod (CNRS/EHESS), France.
<recanati@ehess.fr>
"Indexical concepts"
Following Strawson, Perry and
others, we can think of concepts as mental files in which we store information
concerning the reference of the concept.
Indexical concepts (e.g. demonstrative concepts such as "that
man") can be construed as special files whose very existence is contingent
upon the existence of certain contextual relations to entities in the
environment. The reference of an indexical concept is the entity which stands
in the appropriate contextual relation to the thinker in whose thought the
concept occurs. The nature of the contextual relation which the reference must
satisfy determines the type of the
concept.
In this paper the notion of an indexical concept will be extended so as
to encompass a vast class of fairly ordinary concepts. It will be argued that
natural-kind concepts such as the concept of water, and recognitional concepts
more generally, are indexical concepts based on a certain type of relation to
the reference of the concept.
Like demonstrative concepts, recognitional concepts presuppose some form
of acquaintance with the reference, hence the extension of the notion of
indexical concept which I have just suggested may seem natural. But what about
cases in which the subject is not acquainted with the reference but has merely
second-hand knowledge of it? I will argue that, in such cases, the subject
possesses a deferential concept, and
that deferential concepts themselves are indexical. While the indexical
concepts talked about so far serve as repository for information gained in
perception through various relations of acquaintance with the reference,
deferential concepts serve as repository for information gained in
communication through linguistic
relations to the reference.
CARA
SPENCER
Howard University, USA
<cspencer@howard.edu>
"Cognitive
Significance and the Diagonal Proposition: A Two-Dimensional Approach to
Discourse-Internal Identity"
If occurrences e and e' of proper names, demonstratives or
indexicals are used in a discourse, and understanding the discourse requires
participants in it to believe that e and e' are intended to refer to the same
thing, then I will say that there is a discourse-internal
identity between these occurrences of e
and e'. For instance, suppose A and B
are talking. A says, "What can I get you?" and B replies "I'll
have a beer." Plausibly, fully understanding this conversation requires
listeners to believe that A's "you" and B's "I" co-refer,
hence there is a discourse-internal identity between these occurrences of
"you" and "I". Discourse-internal identities are typically
grasped, and believed to be grasped, by all attentive participants in a
conversation, yet propositions about discourse internal identities are rarely
the explicit contents of any utterances in the conversation. This speaks in
favor of characterizing them as presuppositions of the conversation. What I
propose here is an application of the framework offered in Robert Stalnaker's
"Assertion" (1976) that treats propositions about discourse internal
identities as part of the evolving context set of presuppositions. I also
propose a two-dimensionalist extension of the basic solution to deal with the
sorts of discourses in which utterances are best understood as conveying the
diagonal proposition of a two-dimensional propositional concept.
JASON
STANLEY
University of Michigan, USA
<jasoncs@umich.edu>
"Modality
and What is Said"
If, relative to a context, what a sentence says is possible, then what it says
could be true. Following natural philosophical usage, it would thus seem clear
that in assessing an occurrence of a sentence for possibility or necessity, one
is assessing what is said by that occurrence. In this paper, I argue that
natural philosophical usage misleads here. In assessing an occurrence of a
sentence for possibility or necessity, one is not assessing the modal status of
the proposition expressed by that occurrence of the sentence.
KAI-YEE
WONG
The Chinese University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong
<b388758@mailserv.cuhk.edu.hk>
"Two-Dimensionalism,
Context and Reference"
Recently Frank Jackson (From Metaphysics to Ethics, OUP 1998), David Chalmers (The Conscious Mind, OUP 1996), and
Kai-Yee Wong (“Sentence Relativity and The Necessary A Posteriori”, Philosophical
Studies, 1996) have claimed that two-dimensionalism offers a nice
explanation of the possibility of Kripkean a
posteriori necessary truths, such as ‘Water is H2O’ and
‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’. This paper argues that this claim is sound only if
augmented by a relative construal of the a
priori. Section one of the paper outlines the basic two-dimensional ideas
underlying the kind of explanation offered by Jackson, Chalmers and Wong.
Section two presents the ‘two-propositions objection’ against the
two-dimensional explanation. It is argued that such an explanation tends to
invoke two different propositions for each case of a posteriori necessity, one for the attribution of a posteriority and the other for
necessity. This leads to the suggestion that the two-dimensional account is
incomplete without the relativisation of the a priori. Finally remarks are made on the intuitive appeal of the
relative construal.